All the personalities
who have influenced me had ideas to express about human society.
The reason why I believe that Martin Buber has shown most of all
the things I believe about the social organization lies in the
fact that he has been able to explain as clearly. I know him only
because he was often quoted in Herbert Read published articles on
anarchist magazine Freedom. Read was a director of Routledge
publishing house and in 1949 he brought out a translation of
Buber's Paths in Utopia book, the text was a reaffirmation of the
anarchist tradition in socialist thought, ridiculed for decades
both before and after publication of two forms of Idolatry of the
State, that of Fabiani and the Marxist. Since then I have
followed the evolution of sociological theories of Buber and I
was captivated by his lecture on "State and Society",
which condenses a series of theses which, paradoxically, brought
him only hostility. In the fifties, my friend, the architect,
Gabriel Epstein, whose parents lived in the same street in
Jerusalem randomly Buber, I confirmed that the then leadership of
the Labor Party in Israel considered him a saboteur and a
supporter. Three years after a veteran kibbutz told me that for
Buber as he saw it was just an old trombone and clearly to his
death in 1965 the Guardian reported that "in Palestine, his
idea of a double nationalism got him ostracized by orthodox
, which calling him a 'enemy of the people.' " A
philosopher who was able to stand against anyone, but it was a
model of kindness and benevolence, it must have something
important to say. I thought about it and I do not think he's
wrong. He was known as a theologian, but I remember when, in a
BBC television program, he told a priest, perplexed: "I must
confess that I do not like religion much." And one who
suggested that he was said to be a mystic in fact, a rationalist,
rationalism, and that was "the only one of my visions of the
world to allow them to end in 'ism'". The
only time I saw him in person, was in 1956 at King's College in
the Strand, where he held a conference on "What is common",
explaining the philosophy of dialogue exposed in his book I and
Thou, along with his thesis on community and society. He was
inspired by a text by Aldous Huxley who reported their
experiments with mescaline, which had become, to use the phrase
uttered by Buber in a slow and emphatic English, a parable of
what he considered the company separated the Western
individualism . Huxley, in his escape from the "painful
earthly world" under the influence of drugs, he discovered
that his lips, the palms of the hands and genitals (the organs of
communication with others, suggested Buber) had cooled and that
he avoided gaze of those present. Why, Buber said, watching the
other eye could recognize what we have in common. And after that
escape from the ego and from the normal, Huxley's "met with
a deep distrust of others." Huxley mescaline intoxication
considered his mystical experience, but what we call mystics,
Buber said, as what we call creative artists, do not try to
escape from the human situation. "I do not want to leave the
real world of speech, in which demands a response. Remain
attached to the common world until they are torn. " "Deep
in my heart," he confessed, "I love the world more than
you love the spirit," the president was embarrassed and
jumps down to the steep stairs of the stage, to ask questions to
those who ask questions, to be sure you understand what who
wanted to know. For Buber, as explained by Herbert Read, "the
communication of truth, of any 'lesson', depends on the existence
of a condition of reciprocity between teacher and student - every
effective communication is a dialogue ..." Buber has a
different meaning depending on who reads it. For me it is a
philosopher of the company, a sociologist, in fact, that many
decades ago had already understood the nature of the crisis of
capitalism as socialism. "The era of advanced capitalism,"
he wrote, "has shattered the structure of society. The
companies that preceded it was made of several companies: he had
a complex and pluralistic, that gave that particular vitality and
allowed her to resist the totalitarian tendencies inherent in the
centralized state pre-revolutionary. "But the end was in the
throes of Socialism 'idolatry of the state: "If socialism
wants out of the impasse in which it is hunted, it is necessary,
among other things, take the term' Utopia ', dissect and examine
the actual content." Buber was not an anarchist, but a
supporter of what he called pluralist socialism. But the
Socialists have not yet made its own claim to the west and East..
|
Martin
Buber
|
“Why I don't hate the Germans”
Buber was born in Vienna, from a family of
enlightened and emancipated Jews, but after the divorce of their
parents had gone to live with his grandfather in Lemberg,
Austrian Galicia. There
could enjoy "a very short and quivering years of religious
piety" and ended "formal obedience to Jewish law,"
but he also discovered the Pietist sect of Hasidism. While
studying philosophy at Vienna, in the last decade of the
nineteenth century, he met the poet and propagandist and
anarchist Gustav Landauer came into contact with the Zionist
movement. Landauer was collaborator and after the killing of the
latter, after the massacres in the "republic of the
Councils" of Monaco, became the executor. The relationship
was stormy with Zionism. For him, the movement had nothing to do
with hopes for a Jewish state: "Although for many Zionism
has become a mask of pride, the tool to hide their alienation and
lack of roots in Europe, for Buber was the means to create new
roots, the means of last resort to restore sporadic contacts with
the European tradition ", as with the tradition of
cooperative settlements promoted by secular and socialist
pioneers such as Aaron David Gordon. In the midst of the
cataclysm that hit Germany, Buber expatriation in 1938 and was
the chair of social philosophy at the Hebrew University of
Jerusalem. There he found himself more isolated than at any other
time in his life. "During the conflict that preceded and
accompanied the birth of the State of Israel, Buber took a
position (a natural consequence of its spiritual Zionism) that
alienated the sympathy of broad sectors of the Israeli community.
He argued with Judah Magnes, Ernst Simon and others that the only
solution to the Jewish problem was a binational state in which
Arabs and Jews had to live with and that both nations had to
share: this caused him great antipathy and resentment. " In
1951 he was criticized for accepting the Goethe Prize from the
University of Hamburg. They asked him if he had been too quick to
forgive. In response he accepted yet another award in German and
spoke these words, withdrawing it:
About
ten years ago, a considerable number of Germans - had to be
several thousand - under the indirect control of the German
government and the direct one of its representatives, killed
millions of my people, with a procedure prepared and implemented
in a systematic way, whose cruelty organized
not find unmatched in any previous historical event. I, who am a
survivor, I have only formally common humanity with those who
participated in this action. You are so radically removed from
the gathering of human beings, have moved in a sphere of
monstrous inhumanity so inaccessible to my conception, which to
me has not even been able to give birth to hatred. And who am I
to presume to grant a pardon? When I think of the German
people of the times of Auschwitz and Treblinka, come to mind
first of all, many who knew what monstrous things were happening
and there stood against it. But my heart, who knows the
weaknesses of men, he refuses to condemn my neighbor who could
not win on himself to become a martyr. Then he appears in front
of the mass of those who did not know what had kept hidden from
the German public did not try to find out what was truth behind
the rumors. When I think of these men, I think the sense of
anguish, which I know well, the human creature in front of a
truth that is afraid of not being able to bear. And finally I can
think of, thanks to reliable reports, some that are familiar to
me in the eyes, in fact and in his voice, as if they were
friends, who refused to follow orders and have been killed or
killed themselves, or have known what was going on, there are
opposite and have been put to death, or knowing and not being
able to do anything to stop it have committed suicide. I see
these people very close to me, in that special intimacy that
binds us to the dead and sometimes their own. The respect and
affection for these Germans hour fills my heart.
The book Buber's Paths in Utopia, completed in
1945, is a defense and a reaffirmation of the current criticism
of socialist thought from Marx and Engels as "Utopian"
and that this has been ignored in history books and university
courses on political thought. The book puts the light in
particular the anarchist tradition represented by Proudhon,
Kropotkin and Landauer. On the issue of ends and means, put it
this way:
Kropotkin
summed up the view of the bottom ends in a single
sentence: the most complete development of individuality "will
combine with the greatest development in every aspect of
voluntary association, and at every possible level for all
possible purposes, an association that is in flux, which contains
in itself the elements of its life, which takes the form that
best match at any given time to the many battles to be fought in
every field. "This is exactly what he wanted Proudhon in his
more mature development of thought. It may be argued that the
goal of Marxism is not substantially different in its
constitution, but at this point in front of us is a huge gap,
reassembled only by the special current Marxist utopians, a rift
between the transformations to be performed in a future time (not
much time after the victory of the Revolution) on the one hand
and, secondly, the road to the Revolution and beyond of it, a
road that is characterized by a pervasive centralism that does
not allow differences and initiatives individual. The uniformity
as a means must be transformed miraculously into a multiplicity
as an end, the constriction in the wild. Because contrary to what
the socialist utopians and Marxists do not want half related to
the end, he refuses to believe in our faith in the "jump"
the future we now have the exact opposite of what we stand for
and believes instead here and now we must create the space
immediately possible for the thing for which we stand, because it
can come to fruition, does not believe in post-revolutionary
leap, but in the continuity of the revolution.
|
Colin
Ward
|
Kropotkin, but even better Landauer
Buber wrote these words long before the "forty
years wasted" by the imposition of Marxist regimes in
Eastern Europe. But when we look at capitalist society, says
Buber, "we see a society that is inherently poor and
impoverished in the structure every day" (for the structure
of society is defined as the social or community content: you can
say that a society is structurally rich as it is made up of
genuine companies, or by local communities, community work and
their association step by step). Buber makes a comparison between
the ideas of Proudhon and those of Saint-Simon: "Saint-Simon
took account of the reform of the state, Proudhon, the
transformation of society. An authentic reconstruction of society
can begin only by a radical alteration of the relationship
between social order and political order. It can no longer be a
political regime to replace with another, but to bring out,
instead of a political regime implanted about a company, one that
is an expression of society itself. " For Buber,
Kropotkin amplifies the thought of Proudhon, with the simple
contrast between the principles of the struggle for survival and
mutual aid. The initial theory of the State in which he is
considered Kropotkin historically under-substantiated and while
the subsequent arguments seem more useful, expressed in the
French edition of 1913 of The Modern Science and Anarchism:
"Throughout the history of civilization have faced two
opposing traditions, two opposing trends: the Roman tradition and
the natural, the Imperial and Federal, the authoritarian and
libertarian. " Buber believes that the step forward made
by Gustav Landauer than Kropotkin lies in his insight on the
question of the state. To Landauer "the state is a
condition, a particular relationship between human beings, a mode
of behavior of men: we destroy it by contracting other
relationships, by behaving differently." Buber examines
the ideas of Marx, Engels, Lenin and Stalin, and shows how their
attitudes toward unions and workers' councils, as against the old
Russian institutions, the mir and the artel, these were seen only
as instruments of political struggle . "From the point of
view of Leninism," said Stalin "collective economies
and even the Soviets were seen as a form of organization, a
weapon and nothing but a weapon." In the nature of things,
says Buber, "is not we can expect a little tree turned into
a stick throw the leaves. " Everything in the social
thought of Buber, pushes him to the cooperative movement, whether
it's consumer cooperatives, production or home. It moves from a
foregone conclusion:
For the most part, the management of large cooperative
institutions differs from that of organizations increasingly
capitalist and bureaucratic principle has completely discredited,
in vast areas, voluntary work, once acclaimed as the most
precious and essential to the cooperative movement. This is most
evident in countries where consumer groups have increasingly
cooperated with the State and local authorities; Charles Gide had
certainly not wrong when he exhorted us not forget the history of
the wolf in sheepskin and expressed the fear that instead of make
"cooperative" state, we only managed to make "static"
cooperatives. Those of us who have spent a lifetime as members
of nomal consumer cooperatives in England will no doubt agree. We
have seen the internal politics of the cooperative movement used
as a starting point to get to a post by left-wing politicians. At
the same time we have observed (and this is something that Buber
had failed to notice) as the leaders of the local offices of
consumer cooperatives were lured with wages from double chains of
supermarkets capitalist. Buber, however, had come to examine
the repeated attempts in the previous century and a half, in
Europe and America, to found cooperative settlements, discovering
a need to use the word failure is not only for experiments after
a short life had completely dissolved or had taken what he
considered a capitalist framework, thus dropping the opponent's
court, but also exerted a similar criticism of attempts that
aimed at a wider co-operative way of life, but isolation from the
rest of the world. In fact, the real task, really new common
structural village begins with their federation, or by their
union on the same principle at work in their internal structure.
Even in places like the Dukhobors in Canada, where a sort of
federation itself continues to be isolated and does not exert any
force of attraction and no educational influence to society as a
whole, the result is that you do not even begin to do that task
and then there is no reason to speak of success in a socialist
direction. Interestingly, Kropotkin sees these two elements -
isolation of settlements between them and their isolation from
the rest of society - the actual causes of failure as it is
normally. If the "full cooperative", which combine
production and consumption is integrated agriculture and
industry, must become the cell of a new society, it is necessary,
according to Buber, that "the emergence of a network of
settlements, on a territorial basis and federal structure, with
no dogmatic rigidity, enabling the coexistence side by side of
different forms of society, but always pointing to a new organic
whole. " In 1945 he was convinced that there was an attempt
"which authorizes us to speak of success in a socialist
direction, and this is the common Jewish village in its various
forms, founded in Palestine." He called the kibbutz movement
a signal of non-failure (could not say successful) because he
knew too well the difficulties and disappointments of the
intrusion of politics and "regrettable fact that the
all-important attitude of good-neighborly relations is not been
adequately developed, "and how much still remained to be
done. There are two poles of Socialism, Buber concludes, among
which we can choose: "One must designate it - given that
Russia has not yet undergone a substantial change - with the
formidable name of Moscow. The other would be proud to call it
Jerusalem. "
Cooperation and federalism
This polarity has not worked well. Almost half a
century later there can be no essential changes in Moscow,
although not in the sense advocated by Buber. When in Jerusalem,
few people would see as a beacon of socialism. Already in the
twenties Buber warned that if the Zionist movement in Palestine,
the Jews had not found a way to live with the Arabs and next to
them, they would be living with their hostility. In 1950,
during celebrations for the twenty-fifth anniversary of the
Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Buber held a conference on
"Society and State." He began by quoting the opinion of
sociologist Robert MacIver, for which "identify the social
with the political means to be guilty of the grossest of
confusion, which prevents the understanding of both companies
throughout the state." It then passed in review the
arguments of scholars from Plato to Bertrand Russell, who treated
the relationship between social principle and political
principle. The first is seen in the power, authority, dominion,
the second refers to families, groups, union, cooperative bodies
and communities. It is the same distinction made by Jayaprakash
Narayan between Rajni (state policy) and lokniti (People's
Political). For Buber the fact that people feel threatened by
each other gives the state defined its unifying power, it depends
on the instinct of preservation of society itself, the external
crisis triggered when the underlying action is required than in
domestic crises. The administration of the social sphere, he
claims, is the equivalent of the government in the political
sphere. But all forms of government have this in common: each has
more power than is required by the given situation: in practice
to have this excess capacity is what gives us the political
power. The extent of this excess, which of course can not be
calculated precisely, is the exact difference between
Administration and Government. I call it "political
surplus". His justification comes from the state of latent
crisis between nations and within each nation ... The political
principle is always stronger in relation to the social principle,
than the situation requires it. The result is a continuous
reduction of social spontaneity. After reading these words, I
found the terminology of Buber much more valid picture of the
facts of the real world and much more useful than a dozen
conferences of political or social sciences. His words can resize
the political back into its proper measure. For example, put them
in the British politics of the eighties. The government used the
populist language: "rolling back the frontiers of the state"
(set back the boundaries of the state) or "setting the
people free" (free to people), while at the same time
central control policies practiced ferocious and invasive , with
a war against the minimum of independent political attempts of
local authorities. Even voluntary organizations were manipulated
to become transmission belts of government policy. The
"external latent crisis" in the form of the Cold War or
the Falklands campaign was exploited "when action was
required from above" and at the end of the Cold War, is
usefully followed the Gulf War. If
the categories of Buber is observable in a relatively free
society like the UK, apply with overwhelming evidence to the
totalitarian regimes of the twentieth century, which invariably
aimed to destroy all those social institutions that were unable
to rule directly. The importance of the Catholic Church in Poland
and the Lutheran Church in East Germany was not a matter of
religious dogma, but in reality, these institutions were among
the few outbreaks of power alternative left. The continued
reduction of social spontaneity envisioned by Buber is a feature
of the Nazi period in Germany or the Soviet Union of Bolshevism,
as well as Pinochet's Chile and Romania of Ceausescu, as each
survivor recalls. Like Buber, I am convinced that the conflict
between social and political order is a permanent aspect of the
human condition. He did a deducing from the writings of Kropotkin
always optimistic observation that the conflict between
authoritarian and libertarian tradition tradition is present in
the past history as in the next, and Landauer's thesis the idea
that this conflict is not overcome by a revolution..
If
we want to weaken the rule we need to strengthen the society,
because the power of one is the extent of the weakness of the
other.
The exploration of the paths made by Buber
of Utopia, far from accepting things as they are, confirm, works
like many other authors who have influenced me, that the lack of
a road map of Utopia does not mean that there are paths to
destinations more accessible.
Colin Ward
Colin Ward and Martin Buber
by Francesco Codello
The essay is here translated for the first
time in Italian, was added by Colin Ward in a book published
in 1991, in which, under the title Influences. Creative Voices
of Dissent, the English anarchist gathering in one volume his
reading of those authors whom he regarded as his main mentors.
In addition to William Godwin and Mary Wollstonecraft on
education, Alexander Herzen in politics, the economy Peter
Kropotkin, William Richard Lethaby and Walter Segal for
architecture, Patrick Geddes and Paul Goodman for planning,
inserted Ward also Martin Buber in sociology. Martin Buber
(1878-1965) is probably the most representative philosopher of
the twentieth century jew. In libertarian circles he is best
known as author of a good book (Paths in Utopia, 1967) in
which to value, to the detriment of the authoritarian Marxist
socialism, especially the thought of Proudhon, Kropotkin,
Landauer, for the purposes of a new socialism, a humanist and
libertarian. There is a constant relationship between
libertarian and anarchist thought, and Jewish culture (mainly
derived from Ashkenazi and Yiddish language) that Buber is an
important figure that is obviously contaminated, in
particular, with the figure and thought of Gustav Landauer
(the relationship between the two, see the fine essay by
Michael Löwy, Redemption and Utopia, 1992). Buber writes
that Landauer's great insight is that the state is not an
institution that is destroyed by revolutionary action, but
instead is a relationship, a relationship between men, a way
in which humans behave among themselves and therefore it
destroys by adopting other relationships, by behaving with
each other in a different way. Landauer
revalues its tradition of Hassidic Jewish mainly thanks
to the vision of Buber (Martin Buber, 1913), emphasizing the
sociological vision that sets the company to the State. Colin
Ward is part of this strand of anarchism, which runs mainly
from Proudhon, Kropotkin and Landauer, very keen to read the
evolution of social pragmatism. In particular, Ward affects
the relationship Buber held in 1950 at the Hebrew University
of Jerusalem, in some way, developed their own paths in the
arguments presented in Utopia, about the irreconcilability of
society and state. Ward writes: "According to Buber, the
political principle is characterized by power, by authority,
hierarchy and domination. The social principle rather
manifests itself wherever men come together in associations
based on a need or a common interest "(Colin Ward,
Anarchy as an organization, Eleuthera, various editions, p.
18. Anarchy, 2008). Taking up their
theses Ward asked why the political principle is predominant
on the social stresses and, to paraphrase Buber, as the state
appropriates its unifying real political power, thanks to the
feeling of fear that each nation develops when it feels
threatened. "All forms of government have this in common:
they have more power than is justified by the conditions of
the moment, in fact it is this excess capacity to the
provisions which we call political power. The extent of this
excess, which of course can not be calculated precisely, is
the exact difference between the administration and the
government. "This "political surplus" to the
detriment of social spontaneity. The characteristics of the
political power is power, authority, hierarchy and domination,
while those of the social principle is manifest and evident in
all human associations are formed around spontaneous needs and
/ or common interests. This, above all, according to the
analysis of Ward, the most significant insight that resonates
with Buber, in a certain sense, the theory of the collective
strength of Proudhon. This social spontaneity, held in high
esteem by the anarchists, there are no matching programs in
political if not exploitable as a force to mere purposes of
domination and power struggle between different.
Francesco Codello
|
|